Cover page

Series Title

Key Concepts in Political Theory

Title page

Copyright page

Acknowledgements

This brief, but hopefully substantial, introduction to fascist studies owes an obvious debt to a small group of academics, speaking a wide variety of mother tongues, who pioneered the application of methodological empathy to understanding the nature of fascism. Their works became available between the 1960s and when I started my own research into fascism in 1985 and convinced me that the premises on which I was working were not totally aberrant (despite the enduring scepticism of some eminent historians). It is also indebted to a larger number of colleagues who approached fascist studies in a way either influenced by or convergent with my theory of ‘palingenetic ultranationalism’ in a critical but collaborative and generous-hearted spirit. The resulting synergies enabled genuine and rapid progress to be made away from a sustained period dominated by a curious methodological naivety and numerous idiosyncratic theories of fascism of minimal value to practising historians and political scientists.

It is a happy coincidence that the publication of this guide to fascism as a political theory coincides with the formation of the International Association for Comparative Fascist Studies (COMFAS) at the Central European University in Budapest, a fitting symbol of the way what used to be little more than a loose collection of arbitrary, almost amateur guesses about how to write about fascism has grown into a dynamic and cohesive sub-discipline. All those academics cited approvingly in this volume are implicitly acknowledged here, but several helped considerably to improve the first draft, notably my editor at Polity, George Owers (who showed remarkable patience as the project became more protracted and had a decisive impact on the final shape that it took), and my fellow adventurers in research into fascism and neo-fascism, Aristotle Kallis, Paul Jackson, Anton Shekhovtsov, David Roberts and Jakub Drabik.

What sparked my interest in fascism was the synchronicity of Mariella Demartini coming into my life and, with her, a magic portal through which to enter Italian culture, history, and language, just at a time when I was teaching a course on ‘theories of fascism’ with my head of department, Dr Robert Murray, at what was destined to become Oxford Brookes University. He had survived as a soldier fighting with the Anglo-American forces in Italy to defeat fascism, and he now wanted to understand as an academic just what it was he had been fighting and fighting for. It is to Mariella and Robert that this book is dedicated.

Campomorone and Oxford, August 2017

1
Introduction: Why Fascism is a ‘Key Concept’

What then is fascism?

Some sixteen centuries ago, St Augustine of Hippo wrote in Book XI of his Confessions: ‘What then is time? If no one asks me, I know what it is. If I wish to explain it to him who asks, I do not know.’ A similar problem is posed by fascism. Most people who have been educated in the West instinctively ‘know what fascism is’ until they have to explain it to someone else, at which point the attempted definition tends to get increasingly convoluted and incoherent (an assertion that could be tested as a seminar exercise!). The rationale for the addition of this title to Polity’s ‘Key Concepts in Political Theory’ series is that not only is it impossible simply to state ‘what fascism is’ but, a century after the word came into being to refer to a new Italian political movement and programme, its definition as a term of political and historical analysis is still bewilderingly varied and hotly debated. Hence the need for this ‘beginner’s guide’, conceived for those studying at any level in the historical or political sciences who have reached the point where they have been recommended (or, even better, spontaneously feel the need for) a synoptic account of fascist studies, a relatively compact and accessible definition of fascism, and a brief overview of its main features, history and evolution when this definition is applied to actual policies, movements and events.

Study guides in the humanities run the risk of being frustratingly abstract and opaque, reminiscent of an instruction manual for assembling a flat-pack table tennis table which makes sense only once the table has been assembled, leaving some mysterious nuts, bolts and washers left over (I speak from experience). Nevertheless, I hope that what follows will demonstrate that, while fascism may be a frustratingly elusive topic when it comes to identifying the definitional features that distinguish it from other forms of far-right movements and regimes, perhaps for that very reason it can also be a highly absorbing and fulfilling one to study. In the first place, fascism supplies an outstanding example of the sound academic principle that, at an advanced level, no one can study or write the history of any aspect of a major topic in the human sciences effectively without first clarifying its conceptual contours and establishing a ‘working definition’ with due regard to how the discipline has approached it in the past. Second, if the core argument of this volume is accepted, a fascinating narrative emerges of how fascism, since its inauspicious beginnings in March 1919 as a new but insignificant political force launched by a motley assembly of Italian war veterans, grew in the interwar period into a devastating ‘world-historical’ force and continues to impact on contemporary history in a number of ways, despite the radical decline in its support base and potency since 1945. Finally, even if you disagree with the thesis put forward here, it should at least help you to locate where you stand in the ongoing debate about fascism, to formulate what you find unconvincing in what has become the dominant ‘school of thought’ within comparative fascist studies, and to present your own take on fascism more confidently within the context of an essay project or formal programme of studies.

Why fascism is not like a duck

Yet the way ‘fascism’ is bandied about so liberally and assertively in public discourse could suggest that dedicating a whole volume (even a thin one like this) just to clarifying its connotations and surveying the type of historical phenomena it embraces is somewhat ‘over the top’. For many journalists and political commentators, it is clearly self-evident what fascism means. At the height of the US presidential campaign of 2016, for example, Republican candidate Gary Johnson, when asked if Donald Trump was a fascist, replied cryptically: ‘It walks like a duck, quacks like a duck.’ Leaving aside the allusion to the cartoon character Donald Duck, this reply implied that it could be directly deduced from Trump’s political pronouncements and behaviour that he was indeed ‘a duck’, in this case a fascist (Pager 2016). But, as should become obvious after a moment’s reflection, at least to readers of this book if not to presidential candidates or their interviewers, the entity ‘fascism’ cannot be compared to a waterfowl. A duck is an objective, living animal that can be defined biologically in terms of its empirically established family or genus (Anatidae) in the animal kingdom and comprises several objectively identifiable variants (species). ‘Duck’ is thus a taxonomic concept within the natural sciences about whose application to phenomena in the real world there exists an expert consensus, at least within the professional discipline of zoology – though it is worth noting that even the duck family is prone to be confused by untrained eyes with several types of water bird from other branches of evolution that look similar, such as loons, coots, divers, grebes and gallinules.

By contrast, those concerned with the philosophy of the human sciences have shown conclusively that there can be no equivalent consensus about the definition of ‘fascism’ – or of any other generic concept used in making sense of politics, society or history.1 It follows that the meaning of fascism, as of every generic ‘key concept’ in history, social, or political science, is bound to be a subject of debate and disagreement, and any scholarly consensus about its meaning is inevitably both partial (as more research illuminates new facts, relationships and issues and identifies new topics, patterns and interconnections) and ephemeral (as both history and the historiography move on). This is why fascist studies will always be ‘work in progress’, and the key generic concept that lies at their heart will continue to be contested as long as academics consider its characterization a worthy object of intellectual effort.

The narrative history of ‘fascism’ that emerges

It may help prepare the reader for what follows to outline the particular historical narrative that emerges in this volume on the basis of how fascism is being conceptualized here. The first thing to note is that the book will follow standard practice by restricting upper-case ‘Fascism’ to Mussolini’s movement and regime and using lower-case ‘fascism’ for the vast family of movements and associated phenomena to which it gave rise in many other countries, and which is known collectively as ‘generic fascism’. It is generic fascism as a key concept in politics that is the subject here. Once its most commonly used scholarly definition (to be established in chapter 3) is applied, fascism can be seen as playing a central role in shaping a number of momentous events that occurred in the early twentieth century as a direct or indirect result of the alliance of Fascist Italy and Nazi Germany: the war they jointly fought as founders of the ‘Berlin–Rome Axis’ against many Western democracies between 1939 and 1945; the alliance of the Third Reich and the Soviet Union from 1939 to 1941, when Central and Eastern Europe were divided into two ‘spheres of influence’ in accordance with the Molotov–Ribbentrop Pact; and the persecution, forced migration, enslavement, starvation, and systematic mass murder of countless millions of civilians which ensued when the Third Reich unilaterally terminated the pact on 22 June 1941 with a large-scale attack on Russian positions in Poland.

After the Nazi invasion of Russia and the Japanese attack on Pearl Harbor in December 1941, which brought the United States into the war, the European conflict triggered by the rise of fascism, and consolidated by collaboration with home-grown fascist support in Nazi-occupied countries and pro-fascist governments elsewhere, quickly escalated into a truly global one, with major theatres of operations in Europe and in Asia, on land, on oceans and in the skies. No wonder some historians have seen fascism, along with communism, as the dominant factor in shaping history from 1918 to 1945 to the point that they talk of a ‘fascist era’ or of fascism as ‘an epochal movement’. There is some sense in this, since, even if only three fully fledged fascist regimes were established – those in Italy under Benito Mussolini, in Germany under Adolf Hitler and in Croatia under Ante Pavelić, and only the first two in peacetime – numerous movements trying to emulate them sprang up in Europeanized countries, some serving as puppet governments and thus proving vital to Nazism’s success in maintaining control of the ‘New European Order’ for as long as it did. In addition, a number of dictatorships ‘fascistized’ themselves in Europe and Latin America as a mark of fascism’s apparent hegemony and its prospects of ultimate victory in the modern political age.

After 1945, the political space for fascism was drastically reduced, and the concept itself can be argued to have long since lost its ‘key’ status in the contemporary political world. But we shall see that, when an ideological definition of fascism, rather than one that stresses its interwar manifestation as a uniformed paramilitary movement or totalitarian state, is applied to post-1945 history, it highlights the existence at any one time of many hundreds of formations and activities (whether in the form of parties, movements, groupuscules, websites or fanatical loners) dedicated to the core ideals of their ‘classic’ interwar models, albeit significantly revised and updated so as to combat the new enemies of their ultimate cause. Moreover, the persistence of fascist fanaticism about awakening slumbering forces of extreme nationalism and racism, even in just one isolated individual, poses a continuing risk of causing sporadic but potentially devastating terrorist attacks on civil society. This suggests that many thousands of disoriented individuals who feel unable to tolerate what they see as the cultural chaos or ‘decadence’ of the modern world persist in seeing the defeat of the Axis powers as a historical catastrophe. Undaunted, they still long to play a part in inaugurating a new fascist era, or at least in keeping fascist ideals alive, by exploiting any situation or technology which allows them to transmit the urgency of the need for national or racial rebirth based on their ideals of a more homogeneous, more heroic, more epic civilization.

More reasons to dedicate a volume to fascism as a ‘Key Concept in Political Theory’

‘Fascism’ deserves to be included in Polity’s series not just for its decisive impact on the course of interwar history or because, even if the fascist utopia lives out a subsistence existence in marginalized political counter-cultures all over the Westernized world, it can still inspire acts of extreme violence. It is also important for the term to be used precisely and forensically wherever possible because of two widespread misuses, or abuses, of it as a concept that have seeped into public discourse and into the language of the media, compromising its precision and analytical value. On the one hand, it has been widely reduced to a colloquialism for any political system, state policy or example of social mores that is held to limit personal freedom, individual choice and self-expression in a manipulative or authoritarian spirit. The campaign to raise awareness of global warming, the state-sponsored fluoridation of water, the machinations of big business, the bureaucracy of the European Union, government attempts to encourage the public to stop smoking, political correctness, the damage that the fashion industry does to self-image and healthy eating habits, even the state taxation system – all have been tarred with the brush of fascism. Nor is this dilution of the term’s meaning unique to the West. In 2002 the Muslim creationist Adnan Oktar, also known as Harun Yahya (2002), published Fascism: The Bloody Ideology of Darwinism.

A second area in which the term is subject to distortion is in political commentary, debate and protest. To call opponents ‘fascist’ instantly delegitimizes and demonizes them in the eyes of their critics, whether they are the Republican Tea Party, President Obama, Donald Trump, Vladimir Putin, Saddam Hussein, Bashar al-Assad, the state of Israel, the US federal state, the Brussels Eurocracy, or any anti-socialist dictatorship, anti-populist or excessively populist force. After 9/11, it became common for political Islam (Islamism, or, more precisely, global Salafi jihad) to be referred to as ‘Islamofascism’, a use sanctioned by George W. Bush. More recently, during the Russian–Ukrainian conflict, both sides called each other fascists. Meanwhile, some journalists writing for the ‘quality press’ assure us that China has mutated from a communist into a fascist state (e.g. Becker 2002). The most serious effect of such a sloppy use of the term ‘fascism’, whatever its cathartic effect as a pejorative or expletive term, is that it has contributed to the profound confusion that prevails about how to describe the advocates of particular right-wing forms of democratic politics who attack multiculturalism, the free movement of labour, the Islamization of society, big government, and international bodies such as the EU and the UN, but do so democratically, from within the institutions of representative government that they have no intention of dismantling. The prevailing term for this increasingly important current in contemporary politics, ‘populism’, raises problematic issues of its own, not least because it is frequently conflated with ‘fascism’, and it will be necessary to return to it in chapter 5.

Because of these two main areas in which the analytical, heuristic value of ‘fascism’ has been eroded and degraded through lack of precision, considerable space will have to be devoted in this volume to establishing the conceptual framework which will be used to outline its pre- and postwar history. However, as we have indicated, this can take place only after the ‘pre-history’ of contemporary attempts to refine its definition and establish its connotations and significance as a concept has been sketched.

The structure of this book

The structure of the book emerges naturally from this agenda. Chapter 2 looks at the rich history of Marxist interpretations of fascism, the first of which were published two years before Mussolini actually became duce, and also provides a sample of the deep confusion that prevailed for decades in fascist studies outside Marxism on definitional issues. The result of this acute lack of consensus was a proliferation of idiosyncratic theories of the term which found minimal resonance or practical application among either historians or political scientists.

Chapter 3 then proposes a particular model, or what Max Weber termed ‘ideal type’,2 of generic fascism, whose adoption by a growing number of researchers all over the world since the 1990s has resulted for the first time in a constant flow of impressive articles, monographs and collections of essays on aspects of generic fascism or particular movements with a high level of internal coherence and complementarity within the field. These two chapters thus offer a sort of ‘narrative history’ of the long, and eventually successful, struggle to provide ‘fascism’ with conceptual and definitional coherence. It has been deliberately organized and shaped to prepare the reader for the particular connotations and applications the term acquires in the book. (It goes without saying that any other expert would have given the term contrasting conceptual contours reflecting his or her own interpretation, in some cases producing a radically different volume in the series.)

Chapter 4 then applies the theoretical approach that has just been established to the interwar period by providing many examples of the way particular fascist phenomena always combine common ideological elements identified by the generic model with highly diverse and idiosyncratic features, a synthesis which gives each individual manifestation of generic fascism its unique texture and ‘personality’ within the historical process.

Following this, chapter 5 offers a synoptic overview of the evolution of postwar and contemporary fascism to illustrate the sheer variety of the species that can be seen as perpetuating the genus to this day (that is, if the ‘working definition’ proposed in this volume is accepted). The chapter hopes to convince the reader that, even though the ‘era of fascism’ died symbolically with the shooting of Mussolini by partisans near the shore of Lake Como and with Hitler’s suicide in his Berlin bunker in April 1945, the dreams they held of an ultranationalist new order endure on an international scale that they could never have imagined, though often with forms, modes of transmission, contents, tactics and utopian goals which would be barely recognizable to either of them.

The book ends with a postscript (chapter 6) which suggests the key principles of comparative fascist studies to be taken away by students for their own work. It then recommends how even those new to this specialist area might be able to make a substantive contribution to its further progress through the deliberate choice of topics and research questions which are informed by the latest trends and issues evident from recent publications, to which this slim volume can only allude. If they choose to do so, they would be joining an academic community engaged in a sub-discipline which, after a long period of adolescence, seems finally to be entering a dynamic stage of productive maturity and truly international productivity. Long gone are the days when one of the most eminent anglophone experts on Italian Fascism of the time reacted to my sheepish confession that I was writing a doctoral thesis on fascist ideology with the encouraging words: ‘My boy, there is no such thing. Have another glass of sherry’.

Notes